Before
Gettier, an historical account brings one up to date?
Justified true belief is one definition of
knowledge that states
in
order to know that a given proposition is true, one must not only
believe the relevant true proposition, but one must also have
justification for doing so. In more formal terms, a subject
S knows that a proposition
P is true
if, and only if:
- P is true
- S believes that P is true, and
- S is justified in believing that P is true
The 'justified true belief' theory of knowledge suffered a significant setback with the discovery of
Gettier problems, situations in which the above conditions were met but that many philosophers disagree that anything is known.
[1] Robert Nozick suggested a
clarification
of "justification" which he believed eliminates the problem: the
justification has to be such that were the justification false, the
knowledge would be false.
See also
Theory of justification
Validity
Gettier problem
References
^ Chisholm, Roderick (1982). "Knowledge as Justified True Belief". The Foundations of Knowing. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. ISBN 0-8166-1103-3.
***
Knowledge is a familiarity with someone or something, which can include
facts,
information,
descriptions, or
skills acquired through
experience or
education.
It can refer to the theoretical or practical understanding of a
subject. It can be implicit (as with practical skill or expertise) or
explicit (as with the theoretical understanding of a subject); and it
can be more or less formal or systematic.
[1] In
philosophy, the study of knowledge is called
epistemology, and the philosopher
Plato famously defined knowledge as "
justified true belief."
However no single agreed upon definition of knowledge exists, and there
are numerous theories to explain it. The following quote from Bertrand
Russell's "Theory of Knowledge" illustrates the difficulty in defining
knowledge. "The question how knowledge should be defined is perhaps the
most important and difficult of the three with which we shall deal. This
may seem surprising: at first sight it might be thought that knowledge
might be defined as belief which is in agreement with the facts. The
trouble is that no one knows what a belief is, no one knows what a fact
is, and no one knows what sort of agreement between them would make a
belief true. Let us begin with belief."
Knowledge acquisition involves complex
cognitive processes: perception, communication, association and reasoning; while knowledge is also said to be related to the capacity of
acknowledgment in human beings.
[2]
Theories of knowledge
“ |
The eventual demarcation of
philosophy from science was made possible by the notion that
philosophy's core was "theory of knowledge," a theory distinct from the
sciences because it was their foundation… Without this idea of a
"theory of knowledge," it is hard to imagine what "philosophy" could
have been in the age of modern science. |
” |
|
|
The definition of knowledge is a matter of on-going
debate among
philosophers in the field of
epistemology. The classical definition, described but not ultimately endorsed by
Plato,
[3] specifies that a
statement must meet three
criteria in order to be considered knowledge: it must be
justified,
true, and
believed. Some claim that these conditions are not sufficient, as
Gettier case examples allegedly demonstrate. There are a number of alternatives proposed, including
Robert Nozick's arguments for a requirement that knowledge 'tracks the truth' and
Simon Blackburn's
additional requirement that we do not want to say that those who meet
any of these conditions 'through a defect, flaw, or failure' have
knowledge.
Richard Kirkham suggests that our definition of knowledge requires that the evidence for the belief necessitates its truth.
[4]
In contrast to this approach,
Wittgenstein observed, following
Moore's paradox, that one can say "He believes it, but it isn't so", but not "He knows it, but it isn't so".
[5]
He goes on to argue that these do not correspond to distinct mental
states, but rather to distinct ways of talking about conviction. What is
different here is not the mental state of the speaker, but the activity
in which they are engaged. For example, on this account, to
know
that the kettle is boiling is not to be in a particular state of mind,
but to perform a particular task with the statement that the kettle is
boiling. Wittgenstein sought to bypass the difficulty of definition by
looking to the way "knowledge" is used in natural languages. He saw
knowledge as a case of a
family resemblance.
Following this idea, "knowledge" has been reconstructed as a cluster
concept that points out relevant features but that is not adequately
captured by any definition.
[6]
Communicating knowledge
Symbolic representations
can be used to indicate meaning and can be thought of as a dynamic
process. Hence the transfer of the symbolic representation can be viewed
as one
ascription
process whereby knowledge can be transferred. Other forms of
communication include observation and imitation, verbal exchange, and
audio and video recordings. Philosophers of language and
semioticians construct and analyze theories of knowledge transfer or communication.
[citation needed]
While many would agree that one of the most universal and significant
tools for the transfer of knowledge is writing (of many kinds),
argument over the usefulness of the written word exists however, with
some scholars skeptical of its impact on societies. In his collection of
essays
Technopoly Neil Postman demonstrates the argument against the use of writing through an excerpt from Plato's work
Phaedrus (Postman, Neil (1992)
Technopoly, Vintage, New York, pp 73). In this excerpt the scholar
Socrates
recounts the story of Thamus, the Egyptian king and Theuth the inventor
of the written word. In this story, Theuth presents his new invention
"writing" to King Thamus, telling Thamus that his new invention "will
improve both the wisdom and memory of the Egyptians" (Postman, Neil
(1992) Technopoly, Vintage, New York, pp 74). King Thamus is skeptical
of this new invention and rejects it as a tool of recollection rather
than retained knowledge. He argues that the written word will infect the
Egyptian people with fake knowledge as they will be able to attain
facts and stories from an external source and will no longer be forced
to mentally retain large quantities of knowledge themselves (Postman,
Neil (1992)
Technopoly, Vintage, New York,pp 74).
Andrew Robinson also highlights, in his work
The Origins of Writing,
the possibility for writing to be used to spread false information and
therefore the ability of the written word to decrease social knowledge
(Robinson, Andrew (2003)
The Origins of Writing in Crowley and
Heyer (eds) Communication in History: Technology, Culture, Society,
Boston pp 34). People are often internalizing new information which they
perceive to be knowledge but in reality fill their minds with false
knowledge.
The above points are moot in the modern world. Verbal communication
lends itself to the spread of falsehoods much more so than written, as
there is no record of exactly what was said or who originally said it
(usually neither the source nor the content can be verified). Gossip and
rumors are common examples. As to value of writing, the extent of human
knowledge is now so great that it is only possible to record it and to
communicate it through writing. Major libraries today can have millions
of books of knowledge (in addition to works of fiction). It is only
recently that audio and video technology for recording knowledge have
become available and the use of these still requires replay equipment
and electricity. Verbal teaching and handing down of knowledge is
limited to those few who would have contact with the transmitter person -
far too limited for today's world. Writing is still the most available
and most universal of all forms of recording and transmitting knowledge.
It stands unchallenged as mankind's primary technology of knowledge
transfer down through the ages and to all cultures and languages of the
world.
Situated knowledge
Situated knowledge is knowledge specific to a particular situation.
[7]
Some methods of generating knowledge, such as
trial and error, or learning from
experience, tend to create highly situational knowledge. One of the main attributes of the
scientific method is that the theories it generates are much less situational than knowledge gained by other methods.
[citation needed] Situational knowledge is often embedded in language, culture, or traditions.
[citation needed]
Knowledge generated through experience is called knowledge "a
posteriori", meaning afterwards. The pure existence of a term like "a
posteriori" means this also has a counterpart. In this case that is
knowledge "a priori", meaning before. The knowledge prior to any
experience means that there are certain "assumptions" that one takes for
granted. For example if you are being told about a
chair it is clear to you that the chair is in
space, that it is
3D.
This knowledge is not knowledge that one can "forget", even someone
suffering from amnesia experiences the world in 3D. See also:
a priori and a posteriori.
[citation needed]
Partial knowledge
One discipline of
epistemology focuses on
partial knowledge. In most cases, it is not possible to understand an information domain exhaustively; our knowledge is always
incomplete
or partial. Most real problems have to be solved by taking advantage of
a partial understanding of the problem context and problem data, unlike
the typical math problems one might solve at school, where all data is
given and one is given a complete understanding of formulas necessary to
solve them.
[citation needed]
This idea is also present in the concept of
bounded rationality which assumes that in real life situations people often have a limited amount of information and make decisions accordingly.
Scientific knowledge
The development of the
scientific method has made a significant contribution to how knowledge is acquired. To be termed scientific, a method of
inquiry must be based on gathering
observable and
measurable evidence subject to specific principles of
reasoning and experimentation.
[8] The scientific method consists of the collection of
data through
observation and
experimentation, and the formulation and testing of
hypotheses.
[9] Science, and the nature of scientific knowledge have also become the subject of
Philosophy.
As science itself has developed, knowledge has developed a broader
usage which has been developing within biology/psychology—discussed
elsewhere as
meta-epistemology, or
genetic epistemology, and to some extent related to "
theory of cognitive development".
Note that "
epistemology"
is the study of knowledge and how it is acquired. Science is “the
process used everyday to logically complete thoughts through inference
of facts determined by calculated experiments."
Sir Francis Bacon
was critical in the historical development of the scientific method;
his works established and popularized an inductive methodology for
scientific inquiry. His famous aphorism, "
knowledge is power", is found in the Meditations Sacrae (1597).
[10]
Until recent times, at least in the Western tradition, it was simply
taken for granted that knowledge was something possessed only by humans —
and probably
adult humans at that. Sometimes the notion might stretch to (ii)
Society-as-such,
as in (e.g.) "the knowledge possessed by the Coptic culture" (as
opposed to its individual members), but that was not assured either. Nor
was it usual to consider
unconscious knowledge in any systematic way until this approach was popularized by
Freud.
[11]
Other biological domains where "knowledge" might be said to reside, include: (iii) the
immune system, and (iv) in the
DNA of the genetic code. See the list of four "epistemological domains":
Popper, (1975);
[12] and Traill (2008:
[13] Table S, page 31)—also references by both to
Niels Jerne.
Such considerations seem to call for a separate definition of
"knowledge" to cover the biological systems. For biologists, knowledge
must be usefully
available to the system, though that system need not be conscious. Thus the criteria seem to be:
- The system should apparently be dynamic and self-organizing (unlike a mere book on its own).
- The knowledge must constitute some sort of representation of "the outside world",[14] or ways of dealing with it (directly or indirectly).
- Some way must exist for the system to access this information quickly enough for it to be useful.
Scientific knowledge may not involve a claim to
certainty, maintaining
skepticism
means that a scientist will never be absolutely certain when they are
correct and when they are not. It is thus an irony of proper
scientific method that one must doubt even when correct, in the hopes that this practice will lead to greater convergence on the
truth in general.
[15]
Religious meaning of knowledge
In many expressions of
Christianity, such as
Catholicism and
Anglicanism, knowledge is one of the
seven gifts of the Holy Spirit.
[16]
The
Old Testament's
tree of the knowledge of good and evil
contained the knowledge that separated Man from God: "And the LORD God
said, Behold, the man is become as one of us, to know good and evil…" (
Genesis 3:22)
In
Gnosticism divine knowledge or
gnosis is hoped to be attained. In
Thelema knowledge and conversation with one's Holy Guardian Angel is the purpose of life.
[citation needed]
विद्या दान (Vidya Daan) i.e. knowledge sharing is a major part of
Daan, a
tenet of all
Dharmic Religions.
[17] Hindu Scriptures present two kinds of knowledge,
Paroksh Gyan and
Prataksh Gyan.
Paroksh Gyan (also spelled
Paroksha-Jnana) is secondhand knowledge: knowledge obtained from books, hearsay, etc.
Prataksh Gyan (also spelled
Prataksha-Jnana) is the knowledge borne of direct experience, i.e., knowledge that one discovers for oneself.
[18] Jnana yoga ("path of knowledge") is one of three main types of yoga expounded by
Krishna in the
Bhagavad Gita. (It is compared and contrasted with
Bhakti Yoga and
Karma yoga.)
In Islam, knowledge (Arabic: علم,
ʿilm) is given great significance. "The Knowing" (
al-ʿAlīm) is one of the
99 names reflecting distinct attributes of
God. The
Qur'an asserts that knowledge comes from God (
2:239) and various
hadith encourage the acquisition of knowledge.
Muhammad
is reported to have said "Seek knowledge from the cradle to the grave"
and "Verily the men of knowledge are the inheritors of the prophets".
Islamic scholars, theologians and jurists are often given the title
alim, meaning "knowledgable".
[citation needed]
In
Jewish tradition, knowledge (
Hebrew: דעת
da'ath) is considered one of the most valuable traits a person can acquire. Observant Jews recite three times a day in the
Amidah
"Favor us with knowledge, understanding and discretion that come from
you. Exalted are you, Existent-One, the gracious giver of knowledge."
The
Tanakh states, "A wise man gains power, and a man of knowledge maintains power", and "knowledge is chosen above gold".
See also
References
- ^ http://oxforddictionaries.com/view/entry/m_en_us1261368#m_en_us1261368
- ^ Stanley Cavell, "Knowing and Acknowledging," Must We Mean What We Say? (Cambridge University Press, 2002), 238–266.
- ^ In Plato's Theaetetus, Socrates and Theaetetus discuss three definitions of knowledge:
knowledge as nothing but perception, knowledge as true judgment, and,
finally, knowledge as a true judgment with an account. Each of these
definitions is shown to be unsatisfactory.
- ^ http://www.centenary.edu/attachments/philosophy/aizawa/courses/epistemologyf2008/kirkham1984.pdf
- ^ Ludwig Wittgenstein, On Certainty, remark 42
- ^ Gottschalk-Mazouz,
N. (2008): „Internet and the flow of knowledge“, in: Hrachovec, H.;
Pichler, A. (Hg.): Philosophy of the Information Society. Proceedings of
the 30. International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium Kirchberg am
Wechsel, Austria 2007. Volume 2, Frankfurt, Paris, Lancaster, New
Brunswik: Ontos, S. 215–232. http://www.uni-stuttgart.de/philo/fileadmin/doc/pdf/gottschalk/ngm-internetflow-2008.pdf
- ^ Haraway, Donna 1998. Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective.
- ^ "[4] Rules for the study of natural philosophy", Newton 1999, pp. 794–6, from the General Scholium, which follows Book 3, The System of the World.
- ^ scientific method, Merriam-Webster Dictionary.
- ^ "Sir Francis Bacon - Quotationspage.com". Retrieved 2009-07-08.
- ^ There
is quite a good case for this exclusive specialization used by
philosophers, in that it allows for in-depth study of logic-procedures
and other abstractions which are not found elsewhere. However this may
lead to problems whenever the topic spills over into those excluded
domains—e.g. when Kant (following Newton) dismissed Space and Time as axiomatically "transcendental" and "a priori" — a claim later disproved by Piaget's clinical studies. It also seems likely that the vexed problem of "infinite regress" can be largely (but not completely) solved by proper attention to how unconscious concepts are actually developed, both during infantile learning and as inherited "pseudo-transcendentals" inherited from the trial-and-error of previous generations. See also "Tacit knowledge".
- Piaget, J., and B.Inhelder (1927 / 1969). The child's conception of time. Routledge & Kegan Paul: London.
- Piaget, J., and B.Inhelder (1948 / 1956). The child's conception of space. Routledge & Kegan Paul: London.
- ^ Popper, K.R. (1975). "The rationality of scientific revolutions"; in Rom Harré (ed.), Problems of Scientific Revolution: Scientific Progress and Obstacles to Progress in the Sciences. Clarendon Press: Oxford.
- ^ http://www.ondwelle.com/OSM02.pdf
- ^ This
"outside world" could include other subsystems within the same
organism—e.g. different "mental levels" corresponding to different
Piagetian stages. See Theory of cognitive development.
- ^ http://philosophybites.com/2007/12/barry-stroud-on.html
- ^ "Part Three, No. 1831". Catechism of the Catholic Church. Retrieved 2007-04-20.
- ^ Knowledge Donation is the primary donation
- ^ Swami Krishnananda. "Chapter 7". The Philosophy of the Panchadasi. The Divine Life Society. Retrieved 2008-07-05.
***
The Theaetetus (
Greek:
Θεαίτητος) is one of
Plato's
dialogues concerning the
nature of knowledge. The framing of the dialogue begins when
Euclides tells his friend
Terpsion that he had written a book many years ago based on what
Socrates had told him of a conversation he'd had with
Theaetetus
when Theaetetus was quite a young man. (Euclides also notes that he'd
had to go back to Socrates to ask some more questions about the speeches
due to his spotty recollection of the account.)
Euclides is prompted to share his book when Terpsion wonders where
he'd been: Euclides, who apparently can usually be found in the
marketplace of
Megara, was walking outside of the city and had happened upon Theaetetus being carried from Corinth to Athens with a case of
dysentery
and a minor war wound; Euclides remarks that Socrates had made some
uncanny predictions about Theaetetus needing to rise to fame. Euclides'
book is read aloud to the two men by a slave boy in the employ of
Euclides.
In this dialogue, Socrates and Theaetetus discuss three definitions of
knowledge: knowledge as nothing but
perception, knowledge as
true judgment, and, finally, knowledge as a
true judgment with an account.
Each of these definitions is shown to be unsatisfactory. The
conversation ends with Socrates' announcement that he has to go to court
to answer to the charges that he has been corrupting the young and
failing to worship Athenian Gods.
Midwife to knowledge
Socrates asks
Theodorus if he knows of any
geometry
students who show particular promise. Theodorus assures him that he
does, but that he does not want to over-praise the boy, lest anyone
suspect he is in love with him. He says that the boy, Theaetetus, is a
young Socrates look-alike, rather homely, with a
snub-nose
and protruding eyes. The two older men spot Theaetetus rubbing himself
down with oil, and Theodorus reviews the facts about him, that he is
intelligent, virile, and an
orphan whose inheritance has been squandered by trustees.
Socrates tells Theaetetus that he cannot make out what knowledge is,
and is looking for a simple formula for it. Theaetetus says he really
has no idea how to answer the question, and Socrates tells him that he
is there to help. Socrates says he has modelled his career after his
midwife
mother. She delivered babies and for his part, Socrates can tell when a
young man is in the throes of trying to give birth to a thought.
Philosophical labor
Socrates thinks that this idea must be identical in meaning, if not in actual words, to
Protagoras'
famous maxim "Man is the measure of all things." Socrates wrestles to
conflate the two ideas, and stirs in for good measure a claim about
Homer being the captain of a team of
Heraclitan
flux theorists. Socrates dictates a complete textbook of logical
fallacies to the bewildered Theaetetus. When Socrates tells the child
that he (Socrates) will later be smaller
without losing an inch
because Theaetetus will have grown relative to him, the child complains
of dizziness (155c). In an often quoted line, Socrates says with delight
that "wonder (thaumazein) belongs to the philosopher". He admonishes
the boy to be patient and bear with his questions, so that his hidden
beliefs may be yanked out into the bright light of day.
Examining the offspring
When Socrates sums up what they have agreed on so far, it becomes
problematic that knowledge is sense perception, for Socrates raises the
question that "When the same wind blows, one of us feels cold and the
other not?" As a result he introduces the idea of Heraclitean flux to
act as a defense to the wind objection. Heracliteanism shows that
"Nothing is in itself just one thing...Everything is in a process of
coming to be". Thus as there is no fixed meaning in things, but they
draw their meaning in a referential difference to other things, the wind
objection can be incorporated into Theaetetus's claim that "Knowledge
is sense perception". As a result they can then continue their inquiry
as to the truth of this claim. It is important to note that the
Heraclitean doctrine of Flux is not the same as the Protagorean
doctrine. The Protagorean is radical truth relativism whereas the
Heraclitean is radical reality relativism. It serves as a supporting
theory to the Protagorean interpretation of Theaetetus's claim, in order
that they might fully inquire as to the validity of this premise.
Socrates admits that it is unfortunate that Protagoras is dead and
cannot defend his idea against people such as himself. He says that the
two of them are "trampling on his orphan" (164e) but the charge remains.
Abusing the "orphan" of Protagoras
Since Protagoras is dead, Socrates puts himself in the sophist's
shoes and tries to do him the favor of defending his idea (166a-168c).
Socrates continues to find more ways to misinterpret and misrepresent
him - "mistreat his orphan." Putting words in the dead
sophist's mouth, Socrates declares that Protagoras asserts with his maxim that all things are in
motion and whatever seems to be the case, is the case for the perceiver, whether the
individual or the
state.
At the end of his speech, Socrates admits to Theodorus that if
Protagoras were alive to defend his idea, he would have done a far
better job than Socrates has just done. Theodorus tells Socrates that he
must be kidding, that he has come to the task with boyish vigor.
Theodorus does not claim to be a disciple of Protagoras, but never
contradicts Socrates repeated assertions that he is a friend of
Protagoras. Socrates admits he has used the child's timidity to aid him
in his argument against the doctrine of Protagoras (168d).
Socrates, not at all certain that he has not misrepresented Protagoras in making each man the measure of his own
wisdom,
presses Theodorus on the question of whether any follower of Protagoras
(himself included) would contend that nobody thinks anyone else is
wrong (170c). Theodorus proves to be helpless against Socrates'
confusions. He agrees that Protagoras concedes that those who disagree
with him are correct (171a). In making Protagoras a complete
epistemological
relativist,
where every person's individual perceptions are his reality and his
truth, both Socrates and Theodorus paint Protagoras as maintaining an
absurd position. Socrates says that if Protagoras could pop his head up
through the ground as far as his neck, he would expose Socrates as a
speaker of nonsense, sink out of sight, and take to his heels (171d).
The absent-minded philosopher
Socrates then proceeds to explain why
philosophers
seem clumsy and stupid to the common lot of humanity. Socrates explains
that philosophers are open to mockery because they are not concerned
about what interests most people: they could not care less about the
scandals in their neighbor's house, the tracing of one's ancestry to
Heracles,
and so on. Instead their thinking wanders around contemptuously,
measuring the depths of the earth and contemplating the stars above the
sky. It is here that Socrates draws the classic portrait of the
absent-minded
intellectual
who cannot make his bed or cook a meal (175e). Socrates adds a big
bifurcation to this speech, saying that there are only two kinds of
lives to be lived: a divinely happy one, lived by righteous philosophers
or a godless, miserable one, such as most people live (176-177).
Socrates admits this was a digression that threatens to drown his
original project, which was to define knowledge. Theodorus, the old
geometer, tells Socrates that he finds this sort of thing easier to
follow than his earlier arguments.
The men of flux
Socrates says that the men of flux, like Homer and Heraclitus, are
really hard to talk to because you can't pin them down. When you ask
them a question, he says, they pluck from their quiver a little
aphorism
to let fly at you, and as you try to figure that one out, they wing
another one at you. They leave nothing settled either in discourse, or
in their own minds. Socrates adds that the opposite school of thought,
that teaches of the "immovable whole" is just as hard to talk to
(181a,b). Socrates says he met the father of the idea,
Parmenides, when he was quite young, but does not want to get into another digression over it.
The mind as a bird cage
Perhaps the most delightful talk in the dialogue comes near the end, when Socrates compares the human
mind to a
birdcage.
He says it is one thing to possess knowledge and another to have it
about one, on hand, as it were (199a). Socrates says that as a man goes
hunting about in his mind for knowledge of something, he might grab hold of the wrong thing. He says that mistaking
eleven for
twelve is like going in for a
pigeon and coming up with a
dove (199b). Theaetetus joins in the game, and says that to complete the picture, you need to envision pieces of
ignorance flying around in there with the
birds.
But if this is the case, how would you be able to distinguish between
the birds representing real knowledge and the ones representing false
ones? Are there other birds that represent this type of knowledge?
Socrates comes to the conclusion that this is absurd and therefore he
discards the birdcage analogy.
Socrates and the Jury
After discarding the bird-cage analogy, Socrates and Theaetetus
return to the definition of knowledge as 'true judgement' (200e). This,
Theaetetus argues, is true because it is 'free from mistakes' (200e).
However Socrates introduces an example of a jury in the law-courts,
being persuaded of an opinion by a lawyer. This persuasion is not the
same as knowing the truth, as all is produced is 'conviction' in judging
whatever the lawyers want (201a). Although Theaetetus hopes it is
possible the lawyer will be able to 'persuade' the jury of the truth
(201b), Socrates is unsatisfied as if they are justly persuaded, they
will have true knowledge. However, in Socrates' belief, they cannot make
a correct judgement as they would not have true knowledge (201c). With
this conflict, Socrates decides that true judgement and knowledge must
be different things.
Knowledge as judgement with an account
After distinguishing between knowledge and true judgement, Theaetetus recalls being told that true judgement 'with an account (
logos) equates to knowledge (201d). Things without an account are 'unknowable', while things with an account are 'knowable'.
Socrates responds by telling of a dream, in which he overheard people
talking of primary elements (201e). These primary elements can only be
named, they cannot be thought of as existing or not - he gives examples
of words like 'itself, or that, each, alone or this' (202a). While they
can be added to other words, they by themselves are just a name. When
these elements are added together, Socrates says that a 'complex' is
formed (202b). The primary elements are 'unaccountable and unknowable,
but perceivable' while the complexes are 'knowable and expressible' and
so can be objects of 'true judgement' (202b). He concludes his dream by
agreeing with Theaetetus that knowledge is 'true judgement with an
account' (202c).
However, Socrates exposes some difficulties by examining letters. He
takes the first two letters of his name, S and O to wonder if the
syllable 'So' is knowable while the individual letters are not (203b-d).
Theaetetus finds the idea strange, so Socrates deduces that in order to
know the syllable, the letters must be known first (203e). Socrates
proposes that the syllable can be a 'single form' produced from the
letters. With this in mind, Socrates considers whether the 'sum' and the
'whole' are the same (204a). Theaetetus initially says they are not,
but changes his mind in confusion when Socrates leads him through maths
and the different ways of expressing the number six (204c-205b). After
agreeing this, Socrates returns to the subject of syllables and letters
to conclude from Theaetetus' answers that syllables are different from
letters and cannot contain letters (205b). Theaetetus admits this idea
is ridiculous (205c). Socrates returns to talking about elements and
complexes to propose that they are in the same class, as they have 'no
parts and [are] a single form' (205d).
Socrates sums up this reversal by remarking that if anyone tries to
tell them the complex is knowable and expressable while the element is
the opposite, 'we had better not listen to him' (205e). He cites the
example of a musician distinguishing individual notes (conceded to be
elements of music) to propose that elements are 'much more clearly
known'(206b).
Socrates proposes an account to be 'making one's thought apparent
vocally by means of words and verbal expressions' (206d). However, he
wonders if that is so, everyone will be able to make judgement 'with an
account' as they can all (except for the deaf and dumb) vocalize and
express opinions on matters (206e). Socrates examines it further by
suggesting that a man who can vocalize his judgement must be able to
make reference to the primary elements of the subject (207a). Giving an
example of defining a wagon by its individual parts (207a), agreement is
reached that an account is 'going through a thing element by
element'(207d). Socrates questions Theaetetus by drawing on his learning
of how to write, and the idea that if you misplace individual elements
(letters) of a name, that does not mean you have knowledge of it (208a).
This finishes Socrates' second definition of an account as 'the way to
the whole through the elements' (208c). The third definition Socrates
offers is 'being able to tell some mark by which the object you are
asked about differs from all other things' (208c), giving the example
that the Sun is distinct for its brightness. However, this definition of
an account fails as by getting to know the differentness of an object,
you have to acquire knowledge about it. Thus the answer to the initial
question 'What is knowledge' would be heavily circuitous - correct
judgement accompanied by 'knowledge' of the differentness, which
Socrates admits is 'silly' (210a).
Conclusion
Socrates concludes the dialogue by announcing that all the two have
produced is mere "wind-eggs" and that he must be getting on now to the
courthouse to face his trial being brought against him by Meletus.
Significant references in the dialogue
In this dialogue, Socrates refers to
Epicharmus of Kos as "the prince of Comedy" and
Homer as "the prince of Tragedy", and both as "great masters of either kind of poetry".
[note 1]
This is significant because it is one of the very few extant references
in greater antiquity (Fourth century BC) to Epicharmus and his work.
Another reference is in Plato's
Gorgias dialogue.
- ^ "Summon the great masters of either kind of poetry- Epicharmus, the prince of Comedy, and Homer of Tragedy", Theaetetus, by Plato, section §152e.[1] (translation by Benjamin Jowett[2]).
There is some variability in translation of the passage. Words like
"king", "chief", "leader", "master" are used in the place of "prince" in
different translations. The basic Greek word in Plato is "akroi" from
"akros" meaning topmost or high up. In this context it means "of a
degree highest of its kind" or "consummate" (cf. Liddell & Scott, A
Greek-English Lexicon).[3]
References
Selected secondary literature
- Cornford, F.M., "Plato's Theory of Knowledge: The Theaetetus and The Sophist". Dover, 2003 [first published in 1935].
- Desjardins, Rosemary, "The Rational Enterprise: Logos in Plato's Theaetetus", SUNY, 1990.
- Doull, James (1977). "A Commentary on Plato's Theaetetus". Dionysius I: 5–47.
- Klein, Jacob, "Plato's Trilogy: Theaetetus, The Sophist and the Statesman". University of Chicago Press, 1977.
- Benardete, S., Commentary to Plato's Theaetetus. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984.
- Burnyeat, M.F., The Theaetetus of Plato (with a translation by Jane Levett). Hackett, 1990.
- Campbell, L., The Theaetetus of Plato. Oxford University Press, 1883.
- Heidegger, M., The Essence of Truth. Continuum, 2002.
External links